Talk:Euclid's lemma: Difference between revisions

From Citizendium
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Michael Hardy
(I find this proposed proof questionable.)
 
imported>Michael Hardy
No edit summary
Line 3: Line 3:
: and since gcd(''a'', ''p'') = 1 and ''n'' is an integer, ''b/p'' must also be an integer
: and since gcd(''a'', ''p'') = 1 and ''n'' is an integer, ''b/p'' must also be an integer


I'm afraid you've lost me.  How can you draw this conclusion without assuming either Euclid's lemma or uniqueness of prime factorization (the first of which certainly involves circular reasoning and is thus a logical fallacy, and the secdon of which is vulnerable to the same danger since Euclid's lemma is often used for proving uniqueness of factoriazation)? [[User:Michael Hardy|Michael Hardy]] 20:35, 3 August 2007 (CDT)
I'm afraid you've lost me.  How can you draw this conclusion without assuming either Euclid's lemma or uniqueness of prime factorization (the first of which certainly involves circular reasoning and is thus a logical fallacy, and the secdon of which is vulnerable to the same danger since Euclid's lemma is often used for proving uniqueness of factorazation)? [[User:Michael Hardy|Michael Hardy]] 20:35, 3 August 2007 (CDT)

Revision as of 20:37, 3 August 2007

and since gcd(a, p) = 1 and n is an integer, b/p must also be an integer

I'm afraid you've lost me. How can you draw this conclusion without assuming either Euclid's lemma or uniqueness of prime factorization (the first of which certainly involves circular reasoning and is thus a logical fallacy, and the secdon of which is vulnerable to the same danger since Euclid's lemma is often used for proving uniqueness of factorazation)? Michael Hardy 20:35, 3 August 2007 (CDT)