Fuzzy subset: Difference between revisions

From Citizendium
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Giangiacomo Gerla
No edit summary
mNo edit summary
 
(31 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{subpages}}
{{subpages}}
To be Completed !!
To be Completed !!
{{TOC-right}}
{{TOC|right}}
== Introduction ==
== Introduction ==
The term fuzzy subset is a generalization of the subset concept from set theory. Observe that we can obtain a subset of a given set ''S'' by considering the extension of a ''well defined'' property ''P'' in ''S''. Indeed, the  ''axiom of comprehension'' reads that a subset ''B'' of ''S'' exists whose members are precisely those objects in ''S'' satisfying ''P''. For example if ''S'' is the set of natural numbers and ''P'' is the property "to be prime", then the subset ''B'' of prime numbers is defined. Assume that ''P'' is a vague property as ''"to be big"'', ''"to be young"'': is there a way to define the extension of ''P'' ? For example:
{{Image|Fuzzy1.JPG|left|150px|The fuzzy subset of ''"small numbers"'' and the fuzzy subset of ''"numbers close to 6"''.}}
In the everyday activity it is usual to adopt vague properties as ''"to be small"'', ''"to be close to 6"'' and so on. Now, in set theory given a set ''S'' and a "well defined" property ''P'', the  ''axiom of comprehension'' reads that a subset ''B'' of ''S'' exists whose members are precisely those objects in ''S'' satisfying ''P''. Such a set is called "the extension of ''P'' in ''S''". For example if ''S'' is the set of natural numbers and ''P'' is the property "to be prime", then the subset ''B'' of prime numbers is defined. Assume that ''P'' is a vague property, then the question arises whether there is a way to define notions as ''"the subset of small numbers", "the subset of numbers close to 6"''. An answer to such a question was proposed in 1965 by Lotfi Zadeh and, at the same time, by Dieter Klaua in the framework of multi-valued logic. The idea is to extend the notion of [[characteristic function]].


: is there a precise definition of the notion of ''set of big numbers'' ? 


=== The notion of fuzzy subset ===
'''Definition.''' Let ''S'' be a nonempty set, then a ''fuzzy subset'' of ''S'' is a map ''s'' from ''S'' into the real interval [0,1]. If ''S''<sub>1</sub>,...''S''<sub>''n''</sub> are nonempty sets, then a fuzzy subset of ''S''<sub>1</sub>×. . .×''S''<sub>''n''</sub> is called an ''n-ary fuzzy relation''.
An attempt to give an answer to such a question was proposed in 1965 by Lotfi Zadeh and at the same time, by Dieter Klaua in the framework of multi-valued logic. Now recall that the ''[[characteristic function]]'' of a classical subset ''X'' of ''S'' is the map ''c''<sub>X</sub> : → {0,1} such that ''c<sub>X</sub>''(''x'') = 1 if ''x'' is an element in ''X'' and ''c<sub>X</sub>''(''x'') = 0 otherwise. Obviously, it is possible to identify every subset ''X'' with its characteristic function ''c<sub>X</sub>'' and therefore the extension of a property with a suitable characteristic function. This suggests that we can define the subset of big elements by a generalized characteristic function in which instead of the Boolean algebra {0,1} we can consider, for example, the interval [0,1]. The following is a precise definition.


'''Definition.''' Let ''S'' be a nonempty set, then an ''L''-subset or ''fuzzy subset'' of ''S'' is a map ''s'' from ''S'' into [0,1]. We denote by [0,1]<sup>S</sup> the class of all the fuzzy subsets of ''S''. If S<sub>1</sub>,...S<sub>n</sub> are nonempty sets then a fuzzy subset of S<sub>1</sub>×. . .×S<sub>n</sub> is called an ''n-ary L-relation''.
The elements in [0,1] are interpreted as truth degree and, in accordance, given ''x'' in ''S'', the number ''s''(''x'') is interpreted as the membership degree of ''x'' to ''s''. We say that a fuzzy subset ''s'' is ''crisp'' if ''s''(''x'') is in {0,1} for every ''x'' in ''S''. By associating every classical subsets of ''S'' with its characteristic function, we can identify the subsets of ''S'' with the crisp fuzzy subsets. In particular we call ''"empty subset"'' of ''S'' the fuzzy subset of ''S'' constantly equal to 0. Notice that in such a way different sets have different empty subsets and therefore there is not a unique empty subset as in set theory.
The elements in [0,1] are interpreted as truth values and, in accordance, for every ''x'' in ''S'', the number ''s(x)'' is interpreted as the membership degree of ''x'' to ''s''. We say that a fuzzy subset ''s'' is ''crisp'' if ''s''(''x'') is in {0,1} for every ''x'' in S. By associating every classical subsets of ''S'' with its characteristic function, we can identify the subsets of ''S'' with the crisp fuzzy subsets. In particular we call ''"empty subset"'' of ''S'' the fuzzy subset of ''S'' constantly equal to 0. Notice that in such a way there is not a unique empty subsets.


=== Some set-theoretical notions for fuzzy subsets ===
== Some set-theoretical notions ==
In classical mathematics the definitions of union, intersection and complement are related with the interpretation of the basic logical connectives <math>\vee, \wedge, \neg</math>. In order to define the same operations for fuzzy subsets, we have to fix suitable operations <math> \oplus, \otimes</math> and ~ in [0,1] to interpret these connectives. Once this was done, we can set
{{Image|Fuzzy2.JPG|right|150px|The intersection of the ''"fuzzy subset of small numbers"'' with the ''"fuzzy subset of numbers close to 6"'' (obtained by the minimum and the product).}}
 
In classical mathematics the definitions of union, intersection and complement are related with the interpretation of the basic logical connectives <math>\vee, \wedge, \neg</math>. In order to define the same operations for the fuzzy subsets of a given set, we have to fix suitable operations <math> \oplus, \otimes</math> and <math>\backsim </math> in [0,1] to interpret these connectives. Once this was done, we can define these operations by the equations


:<math>(s\cup t)(x) = s(x)\oplus t(x)</math>,  
:<math>(s\cup t)(x) = s(x)\oplus t(x)</math>,  
Line 21: Line 21:
:<math>(s\cap t)(x) = s(x)\otimes t(x)</math>,  
:<math>(s\cap t)(x) = s(x)\otimes t(x)</math>,  


:<math>(-s)(x) = ~s(x)</math>.  
:<math>(-s)(x) = \backsim s(x)</math>.  
 
 
In such a way an algebraic structure <math>([0,1]^S, \cup, \cap, -, \emptyset, S)</math> is defined and this structure is the direct power of the structure <math>([0,1],\oplus, \otimes,</math> ~,0 ,1) with index set ''S''. In Zadeh's original papers the operations <math> \oplus, \otimes</math>, '''~''' are defined by setting for every ''x'' and ''y'' in [0,1]:


:<math> x\otimes y </math> = min(''x'', ''y'') ; <math> x\oplus y </math> = max(''x'',''y'') ; <math> ~x </math> = 1-''x''.
If we denote by [0,1]<sup>S</sup> the class of all the fuzzy subsets of ''S'', then an algebraic structure <math>([0,1]^S, \cup, \cap, -, \emptyset, S)</math> is defined. This structure is the [[direct power]] of the structure <math>([0,1],\oplus, \otimes,\backsim,0 ,1)</math> with index set ''S''. In Zadeh's original papers the operations <math> \oplus, \otimes, \backsim </math> are defined by setting for every ''x'' and ''y'' in [0,1]:


In such a case <math>([0,1]^F, \cup, \cap, -, \emptyset, S)</math> is a complete, completely distributive lattice with an involution. Several authors prefer to consider different operations, as an example to assume that <math>\otimes</math> is a [[triangular norm]] in [0,1] and that <math>\oplus </math> is the corresponding [[triangular co-norm]].
:<math> x\otimes y = min(x, y)</math> <math> x\oplus y  = max(x,y)</math> <math> \backsim x = 1-x</math>.


In such a case <math>([0,1]^S, \cup, \cap, -, \emptyset, S)</math> is a complete, completely distributive lattice with an involution. Usually one assumes that <math>\otimes</math> is a [[triangular norm]] in [0,1] and that <math>\oplus </math> is the corresponding [[triangular co-norm]] defined by setting <math> x\oplus y = \backsim ((\backsim x)\otimes (\backsim y))</math>. For example, the picture represents the intersection of the fuzzy subset of small number with the fuzzy subset of numbers close to 6 obtained by the minimum and the product.
In all the cases the interpretation of a logical connective is ''conservative'' in the sense that its restriction to {0,1} coincides with the classical one. This entails that the map associating any subset ''X'' of a set ''S'' with the related characteristic function is an embedding of the Boolean algebra <math>(\{0,1\}^S, \cup, \cap, -, \emptyset, S)</math> into the algebra <math>(L^S, \cup, \cap, -, \emptyset, S)</math>.
In all the cases the interpretation of a logical connective is ''conservative'' in the sense that its restriction to {0,1} coincides with the classical one. This entails that the map associating any subset ''X'' of a set ''S'' with the related characteristic function is an embedding of the Boolean algebra <math>(\{0,1\}^S, \cup, \cap, -, \emptyset, S)</math> into the algebra <math>(L^S, \cup, \cap, -, \emptyset, S)</math>.


===Valuation structures===
==L-subsets==
In the framework of [[fuzzy logic]] usually one admits sets of truth values different from [0,1]. Usually one considers bounded lattices equipped with suitable operations to interpret the logical connectives.
The notion of fuzzy subset can be extended by substituting the interval [0,1] by any [[bounded lattice]] ''L''. Indeed, we define an ''L-subset''as a map ''s'' from a set ''S'' into the lattice ''L''. Again one assumes that in ''L'' suitable operations are defined to interpret the logical connectives and therefore to extend the set theoretical operations. This extension was done mainly in the framework of [[fuzzy logic]].
 
===Truth degree and belief degree: fuzzy logic and probability ===


Many peoples compare fuzzy logic with probability theory since both refer to the interval [0,1]. However, they are conceptually distinct since we have not confuse a degree of truth with a probability measure. To illustrate the difference, consider the following example: Let α be the claim "the rose on the table is red" and imagine we can freely examine such a rose (complete information) but, as a matter of fact, the color looks not exactly red. Then α is neither fully true nor fully false and we can express that by assigning to α a truth degree, as an example 0.8, different from 0 and 1 (fuzziness). This truth degree does not depend on the information we have since it is assigned in a situation of complete information. Now, imagine a world in which all the roses are either clearly red or clearly yellow. In such a world α is either true or false but, inasmuch as we cannot examine the rose on the table, we are not able to know what is the case. Nevertheless, we have an opinion about the possible color of that rose and we could assign to α a number, as an example 0.8, as a subjective measure of our degree of belief in α (probability). In such a case this number depends on the information we have and, for example, it can vary if we have some new information on the taste of the possessor of the rose.
==See also==
* [[Fuzzy logic]]
* [[Fuzzy control system]]
* [[Neuro-fuzzy]]
* [[Fuzzy subalgebra]]
* [[Fuzzy associative matrix]]
* [[FuzzyCLIPS expert system]]
* [[Paradox of the heap]]
* [[Pattern recognition]]
* [[Rough set]]


===See also===
==Bibliography==  
[[Fuzzy logic]]
* Cox E., The Fuzzy Systems Handbook (1994), ISBN 0-12-194270-8  
Fuzzy control system
* Gerla G., Fuzzy logic: Mathematical Tools for Approximate Reasoning, Kluwer, 2001.  
Neuro-fuzzy
* Gottwald S., A treatase on Multi-Valued Logics, Research Studies Press LTD, Baldock 2001.  
Fuzzy subalgebra
* Hájek P., Metamathematics of fuzzy logic. Kluwer 1998.  
Fuzzy associative matrix
* Klaua D., Über einen Ansatz zur mehrwertigen Mengenlehre, Monatsberichte der Deutschen Akademie der Wissenschaften Berlin, vol 7 (1965), pp 859-867.  
FuzzyCLIPS expert system
* Klir G. and Folger T., Fuzzy Sets, Uncertainty, and Information (1988), ISBN 0-13-345984-5.  
Paradox of the heap
* Klir G. and Bo Yuan, Fuzzy Sets and Fuzzy Logic (1995) ISBN 0-13-101171-5  
Pattern recognition
* Kosko B., Fuzzy Thinking: The New Science of Fuzzy Logic (1993), Hyperion. ISBN 0-7868-8021-X  
Rough set
* Novák V., Perfilieva I, Mockor J., Mathematical Principles of Fuzzy Logic, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, (1999).  
* Yager R. and Filev D., Essentials of Fuzzy Modeling and Control (1994), ISBN 0-471-01761-2  
===Bibliography===  
* Zimmermann H., Fuzzy Set Theory and its Applications (2001), ISBN 0-7923-7435-5.  
Cox E., The Fuzzy Systems Handbook (1994), ISBN 0-12-194270-8  
* Zadeh L.A., Fuzzy Sets, Information and Control, 8 (1965) 338-353.[[Category:Suggestion Bot Tag]]
Elkan C.. The Paradoxical Success of Fuzzy Logic. November 1993. Available from Elkan's home page.
Gerla G., Fuzzy logic: Mathematical Tools for Approximate Reasoning, Kluwer, 2001.  
Gottwald S., A treatase on Multi-Valued Logics, Research Studies Press LTD, Baldock 2001.  
Hájek P., Metamathematics of fuzzy logic. Kluwer 1998.  
Höppner F., Klawonn F., Kruse R. and Runkler T., Fuzzy Cluster Analysis (1999), ISBN 0-471-98864-2.
Klaua D., Über einen Ansatz zur mehrwertigen Mengenlehre, Monatsberichte der Deutschen Akademie der Wissenschaften Berlin, vol 7 (1965), pp 859-867.  
Klir G. and Folger T., Fuzzy Sets, Uncertainty, and Information (1988), ISBN 0-13-345984-5.  
Klir G. , UTE H. St. Clair and Bo Yuan Fuzzy Set Theory Foundations and Applications,1997.
Klir G. and Bo Yuan, Fuzzy Sets and Fuzzy Logic (1995) ISBN 0-13-101171-5  
Kosko B., Fuzzy Thinking: The New Science of Fuzzy Logic (1993), Hyperion. ISBN 0-7868-8021-X  
Novák V., Perfilieva I, Mockor J., Mathematical Principles of Fuzzy Logic, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, (1999).  
Yager R. and Filev D., Essentials of Fuzzy Modeling and Control (1994), ISBN 0-471-01761-2  
Zimmermann H., Fuzzy Set Theory and its Applications (2001), ISBN 0-7923-7435-5.  
Zadeh L.A., Fuzzy Sets, Information and Control, 8 (1965) 338-353.

Latest revision as of 16:00, 19 August 2024

This article is developing and not approved.
Main Article
Discussion
Related Articles  [?]
Bibliography  [?]
External Links  [?]
Citable Version  [?]
 
This editable Main Article is under development and subject to a disclaimer.

To be Completed !!

Introduction

The fuzzy subset of "small numbers" and the fuzzy subset of "numbers close to 6".

In the everyday activity it is usual to adopt vague properties as "to be small", "to be close to 6" and so on. Now, in set theory given a set S and a "well defined" property P, the axiom of comprehension reads that a subset B of S exists whose members are precisely those objects in S satisfying P. Such a set is called "the extension of P in S". For example if S is the set of natural numbers and P is the property "to be prime", then the subset B of prime numbers is defined. Assume that P is a vague property, then the question arises whether there is a way to define notions as "the subset of small numbers", "the subset of numbers close to 6". An answer to such a question was proposed in 1965 by Lotfi Zadeh and, at the same time, by Dieter Klaua in the framework of multi-valued logic. The idea is to extend the notion of characteristic function.


Definition. Let S be a nonempty set, then a fuzzy subset of S is a map s from S into the real interval [0,1]. If S1,...Sn are nonempty sets, then a fuzzy subset of S1×. . .×Sn is called an n-ary fuzzy relation.


The elements in [0,1] are interpreted as truth degree and, in accordance, given x in S, the number s(x) is interpreted as the membership degree of x to s. We say that a fuzzy subset s is crisp if s(x) is in {0,1} for every x in S. By associating every classical subsets of S with its characteristic function, we can identify the subsets of S with the crisp fuzzy subsets. In particular we call "empty subset" of S the fuzzy subset of S constantly equal to 0. Notice that in such a way different sets have different empty subsets and therefore there is not a unique empty subset as in set theory.

Some set-theoretical notions

The intersection of the "fuzzy subset of small numbers" with the "fuzzy subset of numbers close to 6" (obtained by the minimum and the product).

In classical mathematics the definitions of union, intersection and complement are related with the interpretation of the basic logical connectives . In order to define the same operations for the fuzzy subsets of a given set, we have to fix suitable operations and in [0,1] to interpret these connectives. Once this was done, we can define these operations by the equations

,
,
.

If we denote by [0,1]S the class of all the fuzzy subsets of S, then an algebraic structure is defined. This structure is the direct power of the structure with index set S. In Zadeh's original papers the operations are defined by setting for every x and y in [0,1]:

 ;  ; .

In such a case is a complete, completely distributive lattice with an involution. Usually one assumes that is a triangular norm in [0,1] and that is the corresponding triangular co-norm defined by setting . For example, the picture represents the intersection of the fuzzy subset of small number with the fuzzy subset of numbers close to 6 obtained by the minimum and the product. In all the cases the interpretation of a logical connective is conservative in the sense that its restriction to {0,1} coincides with the classical one. This entails that the map associating any subset X of a set S with the related characteristic function is an embedding of the Boolean algebra into the algebra .

L-subsets

The notion of fuzzy subset can be extended by substituting the interval [0,1] by any bounded lattice L. Indeed, we define an L-subsetas a map s from a set S into the lattice L. Again one assumes that in L suitable operations are defined to interpret the logical connectives and therefore to extend the set theoretical operations. This extension was done mainly in the framework of fuzzy logic.

See also

Bibliography

  • Cox E., The Fuzzy Systems Handbook (1994), ISBN 0-12-194270-8
  • Gerla G., Fuzzy logic: Mathematical Tools for Approximate Reasoning, Kluwer, 2001.
  • Gottwald S., A treatase on Multi-Valued Logics, Research Studies Press LTD, Baldock 2001.
  • Hájek P., Metamathematics of fuzzy logic. Kluwer 1998.
  • Klaua D., Über einen Ansatz zur mehrwertigen Mengenlehre, Monatsberichte der Deutschen Akademie der Wissenschaften Berlin, vol 7 (1965), pp 859-867.
  • Klir G. and Folger T., Fuzzy Sets, Uncertainty, and Information (1988), ISBN 0-13-345984-5.
  • Klir G. and Bo Yuan, Fuzzy Sets and Fuzzy Logic (1995) ISBN 0-13-101171-5
  • Kosko B., Fuzzy Thinking: The New Science of Fuzzy Logic (1993), Hyperion. ISBN 0-7868-8021-X
  • Novák V., Perfilieva I, Mockor J., Mathematical Principles of Fuzzy Logic, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, (1999).
  • Yager R. and Filev D., Essentials of Fuzzy Modeling and Control (1994), ISBN 0-471-01761-2
  • Zimmermann H., Fuzzy Set Theory and its Applications (2001), ISBN 0-7923-7435-5.
  • Zadeh L.A., Fuzzy Sets, Information and Control, 8 (1965) 338-353.