Philosophy: Difference between revisions
imported>Brian Delaney (Must have one of Nietzsche, Heidegger, Deleuze, Derrida -- Nietzsche's prob'ly best) |
imported>Thomas Simmons mNo edit summary |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
'''Philosophy''', both the field and the concept, is notoriously hard to define.<!-- is it? The question "What is philosophy?" is itself, famously, a vexing philosophical question.--> One approach is to give examples of philosophy. [[G.E. Moore]] is said to have answered the question "what is philosophy?" by gesturing at his bookshelves and saying: "It is what these are all about."<ref>quoted by [[Antony Flew]] in his preface to the first edition of ''A Dictionary of Philosophy'' (1979)</ref> Similarly, a good start at defining "philosophy" would be to explain that it is the main subject of the works of [[Plato]], [[Aristotle]], [[Thomas Aquinas]], [[Thomas Hobbes]], [[René Descartes]], [[Baruch Spinoza]], [[Gottfried Leibniz]], [[John Locke]], [[David Hume]], [[Immanuel Kant]], [[John Stuart Mill]], [[Friedrich Nietzsche]], [[Bertrand Russell]], [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]], [[Hilary Putnam]], and [[P.F. Strawson]]. Any such list, though, would be of necessity partial, and would raise further questions (in the case of most of those mentioned above, for example, some of their published works are not philosophical, so that the list is only really of use if one already understands what is and what is not philosophy). | '''Philosophy''', both the field and the concept, is notoriously hard to define.<!-- is it? The question "What is philosophy?" is itself, famously, a vexing philosophical question.--> One approach is to give examples of philosophy. [[G.E. Moore]] is said to have answered the question "what is philosophy?" by gesturing at his bookshelves and saying: "It is what these are all about."<ref>quoted by [[Antony Flew]] in his preface to the first edition of ''A Dictionary of Philosophy'' (1979)</ref> Similarly, a good start at defining "philosophy" would be to explain that it is the main subject of the works of [[Plato]], [[Aristotle]], [[Thomas Aquinas]], [[Thomas Hobbes]], [[René Descartes]], [[Baruch Spinoza]], [[Gottfried Leibniz]], [[John Locke]], [[David Hume]], [[Immanuel Kant]], [[John Stuart Mill]], [[Friedrich Nietzsche]], [[Bertrand Russell]], [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]], [[Hilary Putnam]], and [[P.F. Strawson]]. Any such list, though, would be of necessity partial, and would raise further questions (in the case of most of those mentioned above, for example, some of their published works are not philosophical, so that the list is only really of use if one already understands what is and what is not philosophy). | ||
Another approach is to list the main topics discussed by philosophers: any such list would include [[metaphysics]], [[epistemology]], [[ethics]], [[logic]], the [[philosophy of language]], the [[philosophy of mind]], and the [[philosophy of science]]. This has the advantage of emphasising the general and abstract nature of most of the subjects of philosophising, but again, any such list will raise further questions; any item in the list either | Another approach is to list the main topics discussed by philosophers: any such list would include [[metaphysics]], [[epistemology]], [[ethics]], [[logic]], the [[philosophy of language]], the [[philosophy of mind]], and the [[philosophy of science]]. This has the advantage of emphasising the general and abstract nature of most of the subjects of philosophising, but again, any such list will raise further questions; any item in the list either explicitly relies upon understanding of the term "philosophy", or does so implicitly by raising the question as to what is a philosophical treatment as opposed to a non-philosophical treatment of, for example, ethics. | ||
Another way to understand philosophy is to examine its historical development. The Greek word was ''philosophia'' (φιλοσοφία), meaning "love of wisdom". ("Philo-" comes from the Greek word ''philein,'' meaning to love, and "-sophy" comes from the ''sophia'', or wisdom.) The word ''philosophos'' (φιλόσοφος) was first used by [[Pythagoras]] to distinguish himself as a seeker of wisdom from those who thought of themselves as the wise (''sophos''; σοφός). By the time of [[Socrates]] the word had come to mean something more like "scientific man" or "learned man". However, the problem with this approach is that the subject itself has changed through history. Originally its scope included ''all'' fields of study, other than history; as recently as the nineteenth century, what we now call "[[science]]" was called "[[natural philosophy]]" (this usage is still to be found in the names of departments, courses, and chairs in some Universities<ref>e.g., [http://www.inference.phy.cam.ac.uk/mackay/ the University of Cambridge] and [http://www.psy.gla.ac.uk/~steve/wsearch/courses.html the University of Glasgow]</ref>). In the last two centuries in particular, however, "philosophy" has come to mean an especially abstract, nonexperimental intellectual endeavour. | Another way to understand philosophy is to examine its historical development. The Greek word was ''philosophia'' (φιλοσοφία), meaning "love of wisdom". ("Philo-" comes from the Greek word ''philein,'' meaning to love, and "-sophy" comes from the ''sophia'', or wisdom.) The word ''philosophos'' (φιλόσοφος) was first used by [[Pythagoras]] to distinguish himself as a seeker of wisdom from those who thought of themselves as the wise (''sophos''; σοφός). By the time of [[Socrates]] the word had come to mean something more like "scientific man" or "learned man". However, the problem with this approach is that the subject itself has changed through history. Originally its scope included ''all'' fields of study, other than history; as recently as the nineteenth century, what we now call "[[science]]" was called "[[natural philosophy]]" (this usage is still to be found in the names of departments, courses, and chairs in some Universities<ref>e.g., [http://www.inference.phy.cam.ac.uk/mackay/ the University of Cambridge] and [http://www.psy.gla.ac.uk/~steve/wsearch/courses.html the University of Glasgow]</ref>). In the last two centuries in particular, however, "philosophy" has come to mean an especially abstract, nonexperimental intellectual endeavour. |
Revision as of 19:38, 15 May 2007
Philosophy, both the field and the concept, is notoriously hard to define. One approach is to give examples of philosophy. G.E. Moore is said to have answered the question "what is philosophy?" by gesturing at his bookshelves and saying: "It is what these are all about."[1] Similarly, a good start at defining "philosophy" would be to explain that it is the main subject of the works of Plato, Aristotle, Thomas Aquinas, Thomas Hobbes, René Descartes, Baruch Spinoza, Gottfried Leibniz, John Locke, David Hume, Immanuel Kant, John Stuart Mill, Friedrich Nietzsche, Bertrand Russell, Ludwig Wittgenstein, Hilary Putnam, and P.F. Strawson. Any such list, though, would be of necessity partial, and would raise further questions (in the case of most of those mentioned above, for example, some of their published works are not philosophical, so that the list is only really of use if one already understands what is and what is not philosophy).
Another approach is to list the main topics discussed by philosophers: any such list would include metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, logic, the philosophy of language, the philosophy of mind, and the philosophy of science. This has the advantage of emphasising the general and abstract nature of most of the subjects of philosophising, but again, any such list will raise further questions; any item in the list either explicitly relies upon understanding of the term "philosophy", or does so implicitly by raising the question as to what is a philosophical treatment as opposed to a non-philosophical treatment of, for example, ethics.
Another way to understand philosophy is to examine its historical development. The Greek word was philosophia (φιλοσοφία), meaning "love of wisdom". ("Philo-" comes from the Greek word philein, meaning to love, and "-sophy" comes from the sophia, or wisdom.) The word philosophos (φιλόσοφος) was first used by Pythagoras to distinguish himself as a seeker of wisdom from those who thought of themselves as the wise (sophos; σοφός). By the time of Socrates the word had come to mean something more like "scientific man" or "learned man". However, the problem with this approach is that the subject itself has changed through history. Originally its scope included all fields of study, other than history; as recently as the nineteenth century, what we now call "science" was called "natural philosophy" (this usage is still to be found in the names of departments, courses, and chairs in some Universities[2]). In the last two centuries in particular, however, "philosophy" has come to mean an especially abstract, nonexperimental intellectual endeavour.
A fourth approach offers more promise. Instead of a list of practitioners and their works, or of the topics that they discuss, we can describe the distinctive techniques of philosophy: what is it that Plato, Descartes, et al. do in their discussions of metaphysics, ethics, etc., which is distinctively philosophical? Very roughly, we might say it is the study of, or wise reflection about, very general things. To elaborate, we might say that philosophy is the study of the meaning and justification of beliefs about the most general, or universal, aspects of things — a study which is carried out not by experimentation or careful observation, but instead typically by formulating problems carefully, offering solutions to them, giving arguments for the solutions, and engaging in dialectic about all of the above. Philosophy studies a huge range of general concepts, such as existence, goodness, knowledge, and beauty. It asks questions such as "What is the good life?" and "Is knowledge even possible?"
Popularly, the word "philosophy" is often used to mean any form of wisdom, or any person's perspective on life (as in "philosophy of life") or basic principles behind or method of achieving something (as in "my philosophy about driving on highways"). That is different from the academic meaning, and it is the academic meaning which is used here.
A brief historical introduction to some leading problems of philosophy
The history of philosophy is vast. There is no way to make sense of it in a few paragraphs; what follows is an abbreviated narrative of a few important strands. This will perhaps give the reader some sense of who some major thinkers were, and what some important philosophical problems were like. Much has been omitted, and we make no claims that these are the most important figures and problems.
Ancient philosophy: what things are, and a focus on virtue
Western philosophy is generally said to have begun with Thales (sixth century B.C.), the first thinker on record to offer a secular answer to a very general question, "What is the first principle, or essential nature, of all things?" We might find Thales' answer, Water, to be strange or amusing, but his achievement lay in asking a general question and offering a secular answer. This began a debate--a strand of what is known as pre-Socratic philosophy, because it predates Socrates--about the ultimate nature (Gk. phusis, φυσις) of things. For instance, Anaximander held this ultimate nature to be The Indefinite; Anaximenes held it to be Air. Such one-word answers are uninformative as summaries of their views, but they show that thinkers did have competing notions of what everything is, ultimately, or in other words, what the ultimate origin and substance of things is. This tradition marked the beginnings of philosophy and of what we now call physics.
Many philosophers accord Socrates (469–399 B.C.) pride of place as the first great Western philosopher. His great achievement, like that of the pre-Socratics, lay not in any particular doctrine, but instead a type of question, and a method of answering it. Socrates reportedly made a habit of questioning the leading Athenian intellects of the day, asking them for a definition or account (the logos) of what they claimed to know about. For example, he asked a famous general, Laches, "What is courage?" Laches offered a definition, to which Socrates would offer a counterexample; the process would repeat until the expert gave up. Socrates, then, would conclude that the person lacked the knowledge that he claimed to have, because genuine knowledge of a thing required the ability to give an account of it. Thus began the central concern of philosophers with the analysis, or offering definitions, of "big" concepts such as virtue and knowledge. The idea is that if we could limn our basic concepts, we might gain a deep understanding of the way the world really is.
Socrates was most exercised with the nature of the good life and of the virtues, such as justice, piety, temperance, and wisdom. His student Plato (c. 427-347 B.C.) took up these ethical concerns. Plato's master work, The Republic, is an elaborate answer to the question, "What is justice?" In answering this question, Plato develops a theory about what goodness is. We cannot say that goodness is any particular good thing, nor is it a collection of all the good things. It seemed to Plato that goodness is something apart from all of its instances. Furthermore, when we have knowledge of goodness--the knowledge of the account or definition of goodness, which Socrates sought--we need not know any particular instance of goodness, but instead something that exists independently of the various instances. What we know is, therefore, the Form of the Good--something "abstract" or general, which has a sort of heavenly existence independent of the messy, uncertain world of particular things. "Heavenly existence" is not mere poetic license either: Plato held the Form of the Good to be God. However that might be, this brings us to one of the most difficult problems of philosophy: the Problem of Universals. There are many entrees this problem, but the reader might get some sense of it by asking: "What sort of thing is goodness, anyway?"
Plato in turn was the teacher of Aristotle (384-322 B.C.), who had a different approach to the Problem of Universals. Whereas Plato asserted the existence of independent, heavenly Forms, Aristotle was much more oriented toward the here-and-now. For Aristotle, goodness is not something over and above what can be found in each good thing; goodness never exists apart from good things, it is merely a quality that be found in each. This reflects Aristotle's empiricism--his focus on what can be known, through sense-perception, of the world of particular things we live in. Plato, by contrast, is regarded as the first representative of rationalism, since he thought that genuine knowledge was not of particular things, but only of abstract Forms like goodness, and could be secured only by rational reflection on our concepts of the Forms. Aristotle wrote voluminously about a vast array of subjects, from what we now call philosophy, to biology, rhetoric, and much more.
Plato and Aristotle each established schools of philosophy--Plato, the famous Academy, members of which were called Academics, and Aristotle, the Lyceum, members of which were called Peripatetics. Other schools arose as well: Epicureanism and Stoicism, which Romans embraced heartily, and which included a strand called Cynicism. These schools--collectively known as Hellenistic philosophy--flourished in Greece and Rome from the fourth century B.C. until the third century A.D. There is no way to explain the differences between these schools in the short space we have, but we can show how themes already raised were played out in the centuries that followed.
Next: the Hellenistic philosophers, focus the discussion on skepticism as a moral doctrine, and the Epicurean and Stoic concern with the virtues.
Medieval philosophy
Anselm and Aquinas on God
Aquinas and Bonaventura on the beginning of the world
The medieval problem of universals
Early modern philosophy: the origins of knowledge
Descartes: skepticism and innate knowledge
Locke: empiricism as a rejection of innatism
Hume: skeptical consequences of the theory of ideas
Reid and the Scottish School reject the theory of ideas
Kant and later philosophers mostly embrace it and move toward 19th century idealism
19th and 20th century philosophy: the rise of the great divide
Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, and later existentialists
Frege and Russell: the rise of formal logic
Moore and Wittgenstein: back to common sense and the constraints of our language games
The great divide: analytic vs. continental
Philosophical subdisciplines
As with any field of academic study, philosophy has a number of subdisciplines. Philosophy in fact seems to have a huge number of subdisciplines, in no small part due to the fact that there tends to be a "philosophy of" nearly everything else that is studied. The beginner is invited particularly to pay attention to logic, metaphysics, philosophy of mind, philosophy of language, epistemology, philosophy of science, ethics, and political philosophy as--arguably, of course--the "central disciplines" of philosophy.
- Aesthetics: the study of basic philosophical questions about art and beauty.
- Epistemology: the study of knowledge, its nature, possibility, and justification.
- Ethics: the study of what makes actions right or wrong, and of how theories of right action can be applied to special moral problems. Subdisciplines include meta-ethics, value theory, theory of conduct, and applied ethics.
- History of philosophy: the study of what (mainly dead) philosophers have written, its interpretation, and who influenced whom. This differs from the history of ideas in that the history of philosophy involves philosophical engagement with the positions and arguments being studied.
- Logic: the study of the standards of correct argumentation.
- Meta-philosophy: the study of philosophical method and the goals of philosophy.
- Metaphysics: the study of the most basic categories of things, such as existence, objects, properties, causality, and so forth.
- Philosophy of biology: the philosophical study of some basic concepts of biology, including the notion of a species.
- Philosophy of education: the philosophical study of the purpose and most basic methods of education or learning.
- Philosophy of language: the philosophical study of the concepts of meaning and truth.
- Philosophy of law and Jurisprudence: are the study of the basis of law (authority and relevance), and its link with morality.
- Philosophy of mind: the philosophical study of the nature of the mind, and its relation to the body and the rest of the world.
- Philosophy of perception: the philosophical study of topics related to perception, especially the question what the "immediate objects" of perception are.
- Philosophy of physics: the philosophical study of some basic concepts of physics, including space, time, and force.
- Philosophy of psychology: the philosophical study of some fundamental questions about the methods and concepts of psychology and psychiatry, such as the meaningfulness of Freudian concepts; this is sometimes treated as including philosophy of mind.
- Philosophy of religion: the philosophical study of questions such as the meaning of the concept of God, the rationality of belief in the existence of God, the relationship netween morality and religion, etc.
- Philosophy of science: includes not only, as subdisciplines, the "philosophies of" the special sciences (i.e., physics, biology, etc.), but also questions about induction, scientific method, scientific progress, etc.
- Philosophy of social sciences: the philosophical study of some basic concepts, methods, and presuppositions of social sciences such as sociology and economics.
- Political philosophy: the philosophical study of questions about societies and social interaction, including the nature and justification of the state, justice, freedom, law, and punishment.
There are quite a few others; feel free to complete the list.
How to get started in philosophy
It is a platitude (at least among people who write introductions to philosophy) that everybody has a philosophy, though they might not all realize it or be able to defend it. If you're already interested in studying philosophy, your reason might be to improve the way you live or think somehow, or you simply wish to get acquainted with one of the most ancient areas of human thought. On the other hand, if you don't see what all the fuss is about, it might help to read the motivation to philosophize, which explains what motivates many people to "do philosophy," and get an introduction to philosophical method, which is important to understanding how philosophers think. It might also help to acquaint yourself with some considerations about just what philosophy is.
Applied philosophy
Philosophy has applications. The most obvious applications are those in ethics, applied ethics in particular and in political philosophy. The political philosophies of John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Karl Marx, and John Stuart Mill have shaped and been used to justify governments and their actions. Philosophy of education deserves special mention, as well; progressive education as championed by John Dewey has had a profound impact on educational practices in the United States in the twentieth century.
Other important, but less immediate applications can be found in epistemology, which might help one to regulate one's notions of what knowledge, evidence, and justified belief are. Philosophy of science discusses the underpinnings of the scientific method, among other topics sometimes useful to scientists. Aesthetics can help to interpret discussions of art. Even ontology, surely the most abstract and least practical-seeming branch of philosophy, has had important consequences for logic and computer science. In general, the various "philosophies of," such as philosophy of law, can provide workers in their respective fields with a deeper understanding of the theoretical or conceptual underpinnings of their fields.
Moreover, recently, there has been developing a burgeoning profession devoted to applying philosophy to the problems of ordinary life: philosophical counseling.
Notes
- ↑ quoted by Antony Flew in his preface to the first edition of A Dictionary of Philosophy (1979)
- ↑ e.g., the University of Cambridge and the University of Glasgow