Welfare economics: Difference between revisions

From Citizendium
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Nick Gardner
imported>Nick Gardner
 
(36 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{subpages}}
{{subpages}}
The concept of welfare is concerned with the  well-being of the individual, and the subject matter of welfare economics is the influence of collective decisions upon the  welfare of groups of individuals. The theorems of welfare economics provide the theoretical basis for the benefits of market [[competition]], the determinants of [[economic efficiency]], the practice of [[cost-benefit analysis]] and many other aspects of economic theory.
The term economic welfare denotes the  well-being of the individual, and the subject matter of welfare economics is the influence of collective decisions upon the  welfare of groups of individuals. At the theoretical level welfare economics has  provided limited support for other economic theories, and has contributed to philosophical debates about the role of the state. At the operational level it has been widely applied by economic advisers to the problem of estimating the effects of proposed policy changes upon the well-being of those who would be affected. Welfare economics cannot itself  provide the value judgments that are frequently necessary for its application, and in its applied form it  has to embody judgments provided by the community or its representatives.
 


==Definition==
==Definition==
The definition of the welfare of an individual is the same as the definition of [[utility]] that is presented in the article on that subject, but the problem of defining collective or "social" welfare is greatly complicated by the logical impossibility, noted in that article, of making inter-personal comparisons of utility. The nature of that problem is discussed on the tutorials subpage, where it is noted that no completely satisfactory theoretical solution is available. Applied  welfare economics consequently provides only  partial ad-hoc solutions,  qualified by the need to embody value judgments without totally abandoning the presumption that every individual is the sole judge of his own welfare. In many cases, however, the judgments required are so widely accepted as to present no practical  difficulty. There is general acceptance, for example, that  gains in individual welfare arising from psychotic satisfactions are not admissible components of social welfare.
The definition of the welfare of an individual is the same as the definition of [[utility]] that is presented in the article on that subject, but the problem of defining the welfare of a community is greatly complicated by the logical impossibility of summing  increments of welfare to an individual or of making inter-personal comparisons of utility. The nature of that problem is discussed on the tutorials subpage, where it is noted that no completely satisfactory theoretical solution is available.


==Competition and welfare==
==Theoretical welfare economics==
===The welfare criteria===
The basic definitional criterion of welfare economics  states that economic welfare is increased by an action that  makes somebody better off without making anybody worse off, termed the
[[Pareto efficiency|Pareto criterion]] following its statement by  the Italian economist Vilfredo Pareto <ref> Vilfredo Pareto: ''Manuale d'Economia Politico'', Milan,1906</ref>.


===Efficiency: the Pareto criterion===
A more widely employed criterion, termed the [[Kaldor-Hicks criterion]]<ref> N Kaldor: ''Welfare Propositions of Economists and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility'', Economic Journal, September 1939</ref><ref> J R Hicks: ''The Valuation of Social Income'', Economica, May 1940</ref> which requires that economic welfare is increased by  action that can benefit those who gain from it after they have compensated those who lose from it. It has been criticised as a criterion on the grounds that, unless the compensation is actually paid there could be welfare losses from income redistribution<ref>IMD Little: ''A Critique of Welfare Economics'', Oxford University Press, 1960</ref>.
The aggregate increase in welfare resulting from an action cannot be quantified because interpersonal comparisons of welfare are conceptually impossible. However, it is possible to determine whether an activity increases or  decreases an individual's economic welfare. One way of overcoming the conceptual barrier is to deem that an activity will increase efficiency only if it makes somebody better off without making anybody worse off. Efficiency so defined is termed ''Pareto efficiency'' in honour of the economist, Vilfredo Pareto, who first put that definition  forward. The term ''Pareto efficient''  is  used to describe an ideal state of affairs from which it is impossible to make a change which would make anybody better off without making somebody else worse off. (The Pareto criterion is  often modified for general use by the introduction of the  ''compensation principle'', according to which  efficiency is increased if those who gain as the result of an action could benefit from it after compensating those who lose from it, but it is the unmodified formulation that is referred to below).


===Competition and efficiency===
===The welfare theorems===
The propositions that are  termed the ''fundamental theorems of welfare economics'' define the properties of a market that is in equilibrium and has the hypothetical characteristic of ''perfect  competition'' <ref> The requirements for perfect competition are stated in the article on [[competition]]</ref>.
The fundamental theorems of welfare economics define the properties of an intensely hypothetical economy in which there are markets for everything that is supplied and that supply  every demand, each of which operates in conditions of [[perfect competition]] and [[flexible prices]],  and  which together are in [[general equilibrium]].


====The first fundamental theorem of welfare economics====
In such an economy there are no [[externality|externalities]], no [[spillovers]], no [[external economy|external economies]], and no [[public goods]]; every firm operates on its  [[production possibility frontier]], the price of every product is equal to its [[marginal cost]] of production, every  wage rate is equal to its wage-earner's [[marginal product]], all consumers are perfectly informed about all products and none are influenced by customs, fashions or advertising.
The first theorem states that every economy that is made up of  perfectly competitive markets is Pareto-efficient when in equilibrium.


====The second fundamental theorem of welfare economics====
*The first theorem states that every complete  economy that is entirely made up of perfectly competitive markets is  [[Pareto efficiency|Pareto-efficient]] when in [[general equilibrium]]. 
The second theorem states that the characteristics of a perfectly competitive market can be changed without limit while retaining its Pareto-efficiency, provided that it continues to be perfectly competitive.
*The second theorem states that other characteristics of such an economy  can be changed without limit without departing from  its Pareto-efficient condition, provided that all of its markets  continue to be perfectly competitive.  


====The theorem of the second-best====
The first theorem is a demonstration that an  economy can operate to everyone's satisfaction when each of its members acts solely in his own interests,  in the absence of any organised coordination. It can be regarded as highly restricted formal proof of Adam Smith's contention that the economy itself provides a "hidden hand" which coordinates all economic activity. There is no role for government in the first theorem, but one  implication  of the second theorem is that it is theoretically possible for a government to alter the distribution of wealth without causing an economy to depart from an initially Pareto-efficient condition, provided that it does so without creating departures from perfect competition and flexible pricing. The proviso excludes the use of instruments that alter consumer choice (such as sales taxes, that distort choices between products, and income tax, which distorts the choice between consumption and leisure) leaving only unconditional lump-sum taxes such as a poll tax or a tax on land values.
The practical significance of the fundamental theorems is further limited by the the theorem of the second best, which states that an increase in the competitiveness of a market is nor perfectly competitive, does not necessarily increase efficiency.


==The components of efficiency==
The two welfare theorems have no direct implications for the analysis of real economies because no real economy has the characteristics that they require. They have had some indirect influence, however, as the result of the work of theorists and philosophers who have experimented with the consequences of removing some of the theorems' more unrealistic assumptions with the intention of deriving some general rules concerning the  policies needed to maximise the welfare of the community.  Their findings have generally been controversial and inconclusive.


==Cost-benefit analysis==
==Applied welfare economics==
===[[Cost-benefit analysis]]===  
Welfare criteria provide the basis of the  advice provided to governmental  policy-makers concerning the provision of [[public goods]]. The usefulness of cost-benefit analysis is limited  by  the practical problems of measuring welfare changes, but broad estimates can often be obtained  from observations of consumers' willingness to pay to gain benefits or to avoid disbenefits.


==Other applications==
===[[Competition policy]]===
The conduct of competition (antitrust) policy is complicated by the theorem of welfare economics termed the "theory of the second best" which states that, although perfect competition can be deemed Pareto-efficient, efficiency is not necessarily increased by  the removal of anticompetitive practices in an economy which is not otherwise in a state of perfect competition. In principle that
theorem undermines the rationale of competition policy but its commonsense implication is the need to take account of the relevant interactions when they arise <ref> For example, in a market dominated by a major supplier, the merger of two of its rivals might be a second-best solution.</ref>. The problem of interpersonal comparison seldom arises, but mergers policy is often faced with the difficult problem of setting  an increase in [[allocative efficiency]] against an alternative increase in [[productive efficiency]]. Typically of the practical application of competition policy, many solutions have to be judgmental rather than analytical.


==References==
==References==
<references/>
<references/>

Latest revision as of 10:10, 18 July 2010

This article is developing and not approved.
Main Article
Discussion
Related Articles  [?]
Bibliography  [?]
External Links  [?]
Citable Version  [?]
Tutorials [?]
 
This editable Main Article is under development and subject to a disclaimer.

The term economic welfare denotes the well-being of the individual, and the subject matter of welfare economics is the influence of collective decisions upon the welfare of groups of individuals. At the theoretical level welfare economics has provided limited support for other economic theories, and has contributed to philosophical debates about the role of the state. At the operational level it has been widely applied by economic advisers to the problem of estimating the effects of proposed policy changes upon the well-being of those who would be affected. Welfare economics cannot itself provide the value judgments that are frequently necessary for its application, and in its applied form it has to embody judgments provided by the community or its representatives.


Definition

The definition of the welfare of an individual is the same as the definition of utility that is presented in the article on that subject, but the problem of defining the welfare of a community is greatly complicated by the logical impossibility of summing increments of welfare to an individual or of making inter-personal comparisons of utility. The nature of that problem is discussed on the tutorials subpage, where it is noted that no completely satisfactory theoretical solution is available.

Theoretical welfare economics

The welfare criteria

The basic definitional criterion of welfare economics states that economic welfare is increased by an action that makes somebody better off without making anybody worse off, termed the Pareto criterion following its statement by the Italian economist Vilfredo Pareto [1].

A more widely employed criterion, termed the Kaldor-Hicks criterion[2][3] which requires that economic welfare is increased by action that can benefit those who gain from it after they have compensated those who lose from it. It has been criticised as a criterion on the grounds that, unless the compensation is actually paid there could be welfare losses from income redistribution[4].

The welfare theorems

The fundamental theorems of welfare economics define the properties of an intensely hypothetical economy in which there are markets for everything that is supplied and that supply every demand, each of which operates in conditions of perfect competition and flexible prices, and which together are in general equilibrium.

In such an economy there are no externalities, no spillovers, no external economies, and no public goods; every firm operates on its production possibility frontier, the price of every product is equal to its marginal cost of production, every wage rate is equal to its wage-earner's marginal product, all consumers are perfectly informed about all products and none are influenced by customs, fashions or advertising.

  • The first theorem states that every complete economy that is entirely made up of perfectly competitive markets is Pareto-efficient when in general equilibrium.
  • The second theorem states that other characteristics of such an economy can be changed without limit without departing from its Pareto-efficient condition, provided that all of its markets continue to be perfectly competitive.

The first theorem is a demonstration that an economy can operate to everyone's satisfaction when each of its members acts solely in his own interests, in the absence of any organised coordination. It can be regarded as highly restricted formal proof of Adam Smith's contention that the economy itself provides a "hidden hand" which coordinates all economic activity. There is no role for government in the first theorem, but one implication of the second theorem is that it is theoretically possible for a government to alter the distribution of wealth without causing an economy to depart from an initially Pareto-efficient condition, provided that it does so without creating departures from perfect competition and flexible pricing. The proviso excludes the use of instruments that alter consumer choice (such as sales taxes, that distort choices between products, and income tax, which distorts the choice between consumption and leisure) leaving only unconditional lump-sum taxes such as a poll tax or a tax on land values.

The two welfare theorems have no direct implications for the analysis of real economies because no real economy has the characteristics that they require. They have had some indirect influence, however, as the result of the work of theorists and philosophers who have experimented with the consequences of removing some of the theorems' more unrealistic assumptions with the intention of deriving some general rules concerning the policies needed to maximise the welfare of the community. Their findings have generally been controversial and inconclusive.

Applied welfare economics

Cost-benefit analysis

Welfare criteria provide the basis of the advice provided to governmental policy-makers concerning the provision of public goods. The usefulness of cost-benefit analysis is limited by the practical problems of measuring welfare changes, but broad estimates can often be obtained from observations of consumers' willingness to pay to gain benefits or to avoid disbenefits.

Competition policy

The conduct of competition (antitrust) policy is complicated by the theorem of welfare economics termed the "theory of the second best" which states that, although perfect competition can be deemed Pareto-efficient, efficiency is not necessarily increased by the removal of anticompetitive practices in an economy which is not otherwise in a state of perfect competition. In principle that theorem undermines the rationale of competition policy but its commonsense implication is the need to take account of the relevant interactions when they arise [5]. The problem of interpersonal comparison seldom arises, but mergers policy is often faced with the difficult problem of setting an increase in allocative efficiency against an alternative increase in productive efficiency. Typically of the practical application of competition policy, many solutions have to be judgmental rather than analytical.

References

  1. Vilfredo Pareto: Manuale d'Economia Politico, Milan,1906
  2. N Kaldor: Welfare Propositions of Economists and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility, Economic Journal, September 1939
  3. J R Hicks: The Valuation of Social Income, Economica, May 1940
  4. IMD Little: A Critique of Welfare Economics, Oxford University Press, 1960
  5. For example, in a market dominated by a major supplier, the merger of two of its rivals might be a second-best solution.